Aquinas a Threat to Evangelical Seminary Students?

July 17, 2018

I have come upon a most distressing book entitled Evangelical Exodus: Evangelical Seminarians and Their Paths to Rome. The author, Douglas M. Beaumont, argues that the Southern Evangelical Seminary’s focus on classical apologetics, specifically its emphasis on the philosophy of Thomas Aquinas, leads Evangelicals to the Roman Church. Apparently, studying Aquinas is bad for the Evangelical’s health. Beaumont has nine cases to demonstrate his claim.

As a philosophy student, I studied Aquinas. Frankly, I found him helpful in understanding Aristotle. He was also quite useful in understanding the intellectual issues underlying the Reformation. He held many views that differed from the Reformers, but these differences are still seen in the theological positions held by Protestants and Catholics. So he is not simply a footnote to history. In fact, his arguments for the existence of God still persuade and hold a vital place in modern classical apologetics. R.C. Sproul recognized the importance of his contribution to Christian theology, naming him as one of his personal Christian heroes and identifying him as one of the top theologians in Christian history. Norman Geisler, the noted Christian apologist, says that Aquinas has a great deal to say to Evangelical Protestants and that we should listen.

I must admit that at no time in my study of Aquinas did I feel drawn to embrace Catholic doctrine. Some may claim that, but this seems quite farfetched. The brilliance of his intellect cannot compensate for incoherent beliefs expressed by the Holy See. Why Evangelicals would exchange the authority of Scripture for the authority of a priestly hierarchy will not be found in the pages of the Summa Theologica. That cause will be found elsewhere. In my opinion, one promising place to look might be in the analysis given by Keith C. Sewell in his The Crisis of Evangelical Christianity: Roots, Consequences, and Resolutions.

But there is something more insidious in Beaumont’s thesis.
The very idea that the philosophical study of a great mind is somehow dangerous because it leads to possible conversions to the Roman Church seems anti-intellectual–more like a North Korean educational policy designed to exclude non-approved ideas. It’s offputting. I should think that the Evangelical mind would be more hearty and less vulnerable. Frankly, I find his criticisms of SES astonishing.

The status of Aquinas is not simply about theology. It is a matter of intellectual history. Christians who wish to understand the West’s philosophical tradition must study Aquinas. Those who don’t will simply not understand a significant portion of that tradition. A philosophy student who refused to study Plato or Aristotle would not be taken seriously. The failure to study Aquinas falls into the same category. Of course, studying a philosopher does not necessarily mean agreeing with him. In fact, it rarely does. Ask Aristotle about Plato. But to offer up the canard that studying Aquinas’ philosophy leads to spiritual disaster is simply a transparent attempt to suppress thought and discussion. It is an attack on the scholarly study of intellectual history in general and on the classical tradition in particular.

That is a curious thing for a book to attempt to do. In fact, it is a paradigm example of what C.S. Lewis called Bulverism, the practice of assuming that an idea is false and then explaining the motives or influences that would cause someone to advocate such a boneheaded point of view. This avoids any serious efforts of refutation, allowing one to get on with the important and more interesting work of discrediting an idea or an opponent in a public venue. In this case, the classical study of Aquinas is wrong. Why would anyone approve of studying his philosophy? “Well, we don’t have to show that the study is unscholarly or to distinguish what is true and false in his writings. We know that Aquinas is wrong and the study of his ideas worthless–even dangerous! Consequently, people who advocate such study simply want to drive Evangelicals to the Catholic Church and to their spiritual ruin. That is really what they are doing by boneheadedly embracing this Catholic thinker. So let’s get rid of such teachers and exclude Aquinas from the curriculum.”

How adolescently silly and how terribly depressing.

For the opposite view, here is a favorable review by K. Scott Oliphint, a covenantal presuppositionalist from Westminster Theological Seminary (Philadelphia, Pennsylvania, USA): http://themelios.thegospelcoalition.org/review/evangelical-exodus-evangelical-seminarians-and-their-paths-to-rome


TOOLS MAKE US SMART

March 29, 2017

When I taught mathematoolstics and, later, my employment workshop, I gave my students two mottos for the class:

1: The truth is what works;

2: Tools make us smart.

The first motto doesn’t mean that an idea that happens to work is true. That’s a logical mistake. The mark of a true idea is its consistent ability to:

1. Describe what we see,

2. Explain what we see,

3. Predict what we will see, and

4. Empower us to influence results.

That’s what we mean scientifically by an idea being true. In other words, when you use an idea, does it reliably function the way it is supposed to? If it doesn’t, then the idea isn’t true. A new one is needed.

The second motto is a great teacher. Most people are under the mistaken notion that getting things done effectively means that one is smart. That’s misleading. Failure is no more a sure sign of stupidity than is a success a sure sign of brilliance. Intelligence has more to do with our attitudes towards success and failure, not in succeeding or failing.

Here’s why. When we know how to do something well, our minds possess idea maps as tools to get the job done step-by-step. Moreover, those idea maps identify the proper tools to use and how to get and to use them.

Success always depends upon idea maps (proper method) and proper tools. When people don’t have these, they rarely succeed. If one really wants to be smart, the preparation is where that happens. Successful execution depends on getting the method right and finding the proper tools.

In a very real sense, the ideas we use to plan our work are just as much tools as the implements we use to get a job done. And that reveals a secret about failure.

When we fail, that probably means that we are using the wrong method or employing the wrong tools—probably both. Failure’s importance to us comes from what the unsuccessful attempt tells us. What is that? Simply that we need to learn the right method and acquire the right tools before we make another attempt. If we don’t do that, we risk making failure a habit.

The person who is truly smart has learned this lesson. Before attempting any objective, such a person always asks to know the right method and the right tools. This is particularly true when the stakes are high, whether planning a career or fighting an addiction to drugs.


PROFESSOR PAUL BLOOM: DOES EMPATHY MAKE US MORALLY WORSE? (A Review)

March 7, 2017


If the reader is unfamiliar with Professor Bloom’s book (
Against Empathy: the Case for Rational Compassion), the links below will provide a useful summary of his views explaining why empathy makes peoplEmpathye morally worse.  Access to a pdf version of his book is provided at the end.

Lecture: (over 1 hr):  https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=WWWNUa6kmqE 

Bloom summarizes his position (2 min. 48 seconds):  https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=bM1gYZROu94    

Professor Paul Bloom (Yale University) has argued extensively, though not persuasively, against the very notion of empathy.  He asserts that empathy actually makes the world worse.  It is bad morally, and it is fundamentally self-centered.  Admittedly, the unscrupulous may use the empathy of others to deceive and manipulate, but they may use other human traits in a similar fashion, such as affection, the need to belong, the sense of fairness, and even reason.  Bloom wouldn’t attack human reason because it often makes mistakes.  So singling out empathy for such a massive attack seems a curious thing to do.  After all, many “life skills” programs and even the WHO identify empathy as one of the necessary relational skill.  So Professor Bloom’s dismissal of this trait suggests that recognized life skills programs are making students worse and that the WHO is spreading self-centered evil through its publications.

That perhaps seems nutty, but Blooms criticisms make more sense if understood as part of a contemporary rethinking of moral behavior, as interpreted through the lens of evolutionary biology.  Consequently, Bloom cites as an authority a leader in this movement, the Princeton bioethicist, Peter Singer.  He is the ethics expert who:

  1. Equates human beings with animals by applying universally to all sentient creatures the utilitarian moral criterion, “the greatest good for the greatest number”;
  2. Popularized the term speciesism, a notion describing a supposed, illicit human privilege affirming superiority over the animal kingdom; and
  3. Advocates the parental right to kill a newborn up to six months after birth, a radical extension of abortion rights and a denial of human rights to the very young. 

How that supports Bloom’s efforts to label his views successfully as “rational compassion” seems puzzling.  An opinion poll would show that most people would have difficulty accepting as an expert on compassion anyone who advocates killing other human beings for convenience.  But it does put Peter Bloom in the proper context.  Both Singer and Bloom are part of the academic movement dedicated to redefining human personality and behavior in naturalistic, evolutionary terms.  They share the same utilitarian moral theory.  Bloom uses it almost unreflectively to advance his case but fails to make this clear, as if utilitarian ethics were non-controversial.  Within this movement, it’s not.

That’s extremely bad form intellectually.  Though Bloom makes a number of moral claims, he consistently fails to provide any warrant for their moral authority beyond their utility for humankind, which is a typical failing of utilitarian ethical theories.  For what proves useful for the greatest number does not necessarily equate to what is moral.  A doctor treating five young people in desperate need of a donor for kidneys, liver, heart, lung, and a massive skin graft, could not forcibly and morally take these from a sixth healthy patient who came in for a sports’ exam, even if that patient might be an exact tissue match for all five of the doctor’s ill patients.  A criminal court would remain unimpressed by the numerical “five to one” defense to justify the morality of medical murder.

By now, Christians ought to be familiar with this type of thinking.  Materialists with impressive credentials will routinely dismiss Christian morality as actually leading to extremely immoral behavior.  The medieval inquisitions, slavery, the slave trade, and the Nazi extermination of the Jews during World War II are often primary examples of where Christian moral thinking leads.  This proves, allegedly, that Christian morality is a monstrosity, a brutal value theory emerging progressively through a series of brutal, unsophisticated ages. That’s nonsense, of course, but the sheer fantasy of the allegations does not prevent critics from repeating them as serious criticism.  Bloom’s book is simply another example of this dreary history.

I would affirm that Bloom’s analysis of morality is a backdoor attempt to discredit—in the name of reason, of course–Judeo-Christian ideas that for centuries have undergirded institutions of charity in the West, ideas that have informed public policies relative to poverty relief, education, homelessness, public medical care, elder care, and many other issues dealing with the public’s welfare.  The target of his book, empathy, has been used by Christians to persuade the public’s conscience on issues of racial justice, social welfare, child labor, prison reform, childcare, and other matters that have required political action.  Consequently, it is odd to read Professor Bloom’s arguments that–if taken seriously–would imply that Letters from a Birmingham Jail represents Dr. Martin Luther King Jr.’s self-centered and shortsighted attempt to manipulate the American public through empathy to oppose racism.   That is not overstatement.  Bloom might even agree with Dr. King, but much of what this civil rights reformer did was designed to elicit empathy from the majority of Americans so that they would stand with him in his call for racial justice.  Does Bloom really mean to call this self-centered, shortsighted, and manipulative?  I don’t see how he can avoid that conclusion—even if he agrees with Dr. King.

Foundations and Definitions Are Important

It is curious to hear a materialist become exercised over morality.  One must have an authoritative moral theory to start with in order to become morally incensed.  A materialistic universe lacks ethical sensibility.  It neither loves nor hates.  Like the white whale in Moby Dick, it is neither good nor evil; it just is.  It does not favor man, care for his happiness or interests, or seek to guard his future.  From a human point of view, to quote what Richard Dawkins famously claimed, it is characterized by “precisely the properties we should expect if there is, at bottom, no design, no purpose, no evil, no good, nothing but pitiless indifference.”   How dismal!  In the face of such an academic model that describes human beings as organic machines and that deconstructs “morality” as an ethically indifferent instinct produced by amoral evolutionary selection, one might think that Bloom would advance a moral foundation that might legitimize judgments about what makes people morally better or worse.  Unfortunately, that doesn’t happen.  With just a few reservations, Bloom accepts the current model.  He believes that man is a machine, but he is an intelligent one.  And he makes much of intelligence as the true source of morality.  He also believes that what he thinks expresses this intelligence and is, apparently, rationally self-evident.  Though it is puzzling, he doesn’t feel that a rational foundation for moral values is necessary. He simply assumes that his views are morally superior, and that’s enough foundation for his purposes.  The intellectual presumption is astounding.

But a moral principle must have a warrant that gives it authority; else it is just an opinion.  Professor Bloom may believe that his views are “rational,” but that does not make them moral.  Nor does it make them rational.  He may claim that his views would benefit more human beings, but that does not answer the question why doing this would be morally good.  The Human Extinction Movement, for example, would argue–on “moral” grounds–that human beings should go extinct for the good of the planet and its creatures.  That’s a slightly different approach to a morality based on “the greatest good for the greatest number.”  But if man is simply an organic machine like other creatures, then why shouldn’t the interests of animals, fish, reptiles, bacteria, etc., count equally with man’s interests in any moral equation.  In fact, why shouldn’t they count more?  Peter Singer has already claimed that that they should.  According to the model Bloom accepts, human intelligence is simply an evolutionary and cultural difference, not proof of moral superiority over creation.  At the very least, Bloom’s position must lead to the conclusion that man and beasts, in many critical ways, are morally equivalent.

Ignoring the Obvious

Bloom’s presumption is intellectually frustrating.  He ignores the obvious.  It does not require a lawyer to understand that one must define an idea before claiming to be able to recognize an example of it empirically.  More than one criminal case has hinged upon whether a defendant’s act actually matches what the criminal code prohibits.  Sometimes these legal cases are difficult, but in every one of them, the legal code, along with precedent and technical definitions, comes first to clarify the law.  Without legal definitions, no case resolution is even possible.  A legal definition of “murder” or “assault” must first exist before a court can apply it in a particular case.  So definitions are important.  For Bloom to classify “empathy” as moral, immoral, or amoral, he must first define what morality actually is.  He never gets around to doing this.

Though Bloom provides no definition by which to distinguish what is moral from what is not in human behavior, this doesn’t’ seem to bother him.  He is content to cite numbers of people affected by an action to quantify the degree of evil.  Though statistics are not unimportant, they don’t establish a moral principle.  A natural disaster may kill thousands of people; a rapist may molest and kill a female victim.  Both are human tragedies, but only the latter is subject to moral judgment.  A tsunami does not violate any moral laws when it takes life.  Under Blooms own presuppositions, accusing a natural disaster of murder would be irrational.  The rapist, however, falls under both moral and legal sanctions.  This important distinction Bloom does not seem to understand.  He wants to equate the two.  Consequently, he cannot empirically distinguish what is moral from what is not.  He simply assumes that his opinion is enough to substitute for an ontological foundation to make such judgments.  When he does, he gets things wrong, and seems to do it intentionally.  That’s intellectually dishonest, but perhaps he hopes that his readers will not notice. We will see an example in a moment.

Professor Bloom vs. Empathy

To most people, Bloom’s rejection of empathy would appear counterintuitive—if not absurd.  The ability to put ourselves into other people’s shoes seems to be a foundation for positive charitable activity and selfless caring.  In fact, countless Christian sermons and articles exhort believers to empathize with those who suffer and to relieve their pain if they can.  And that’s understandable, for it is Christ who said, “Love your neighbor as yourself.”

Bloom, on the other hand, emphasizes intelligence as the primary factor in moral development, not sentiments that “we would do better without,” as he wrote in an Atlantic article (March 2014).  These sentiments, he claims, must yield to reason if human kind is to have a future.  This, I would argue, is the real point of his book.  Religion, he would claim, emerges from humankind’s non-rational mind.  Intelligence is man’s true moral guide, not irrational, religious sentiments.  Human beings create values, laws, and institutions that make humankind morally better, but intelligence accomplishes this, not instinctive emotion.  That’s an almost platonic sentiment, but he is not a Platonist.  He believes that man is a physical machine, the result of an evolutionary process.  That process has created intelligence within that machine.  That intelligence is the foundation for moral behavior.  Consequently, he believes that a mindless, amoral process has created both mind and morality.  In other words, he believes that a less complicated machine (mindless nature) has created machines of greater sophistication and complexity (human beings with intelligent minds and moral behaviors).  Unlike Darwin, Bloom appears to have no doubts about the naturalistic origins of humankind.

Bloom’s attack on empathy affirms that this sentiment provides no reliable tool to motivate intelligent moral behavior, for empathy is “biased, innumerate, concrete, and myopic.”  It blinds us to long-term consequences, misappropriates resources, disconnects reason from caring, imprisons charitable motivations in “warm-glow” selfishness, and leads to such things as the “morally justified” carpet bombing of a country in order to save its population from oppression.  If one didn’t know any better, one might think that Bloom is saying that evolution didn’t know what it was doing when it gave humans such a sentiment.  For it is the source of all sorts of problems.  As proof, he points to the case of Natalee Holloway who went missing during a trip in 2005.  How is this proof?  Allegedly, the unsuccessful search to find her received 18 times the network coverage than did the contemporaneous famine in the Sudan, which was killing tens of thousands of people.  That tragic famine was the result of war and drought. In fact, drought and famine occur in that nation periodically—with or without war.  Both are happening now in 2017.

Natalee Holloway’s murder was an immoral act.  Drought is tragic and devastating but not immoral.  It is an act of nature, not subject to either moral censure or legal penalty.  Courts don’t put the weather in prison.  The war might be considered immoral, but that’s a bit more complicated.  Just ask the warring parties.  Moreover, the war in Sudan had been going on long before Natalee Holloway’s murder.  The world functionally ignored that war for complicated international reasons that had nothing to do with Holloway’s death.  Of course, the world could have invaded the Sudan and perhaps forced a peace.  It might have stepped up aid to starving people while the war was going on.  No amount of coverage, however, would have stopped the drought and famine.  These still go on periodically.  Nor would more press coverage have stopped the war.  In Holloway’s case, however, such coverage could conceivably step up attempts to find her body and reveal her murderer.  In other words, the coverage could help bring closure to the family and achieve justice.

It’s not clear what Bloom is arguing here.  What network coverage has to do with the morality or immorality of an action he does not coherently explain.  Both Natalee Holloway’s murder and the Sudan’s drought and famine are tragic.  The former was the horrific murder of an American citizen.  That falls under the scope of moral judgment.  The Sudan is more complicated.  The drought is not subject to moral sanction. To the degree that it is the result of drought, neither is the famine. Those have been happening for years.  The warring parties might be criticized morally, but would Bloom favor a United Nation’s invasion to enforce peace?  Would that action be free of unintended consequences?  Or would he favor providing food aid in a war zone?  Would that aid actually get to the people or be used by warlords to control their territories?  And if the amount of news coverage had been reversed in these cases (perhaps purposely to suit Bloom’s priorities), would that have even made a practical difference in the Sudan?  If not, what is Bloom talking about from a utilitarian point of view?  These are legitimate questions, but Bloom never considers them.  He simply mourns Natalee Holloway’s press coverage, as if that would demonstrate some kind of consummate evil and prove empathy’s moral worthlessness.

Bloom’s real problem seems to be that people do not care enough about the things that Paul Bloom wants them to care about—like climate change and massive deaths overseas.  He blames empathy for this, as if he has proved the allegation.  Moreover, he is really upset about it.  This is puzzling.  In a world that would actually follow his advice, it is unclear why his opinion should matter to anyone.  After all, who would really care to empathize?  Perhaps people might thank him for providing a reason to dismiss his concerns out of hand, but Bloom’s own reasoning gives no justification why his views should matter.  Amazingly, he assumes otherwise.  His summary lecture on the subject will take over an hour of a listener’s valuable time.

Reason Alone Can’t Do the Job, So What Else Do We Need

Now Bloom would say that his ethical critique of empathy derives from science and reason.  Unfortunately, that is mere academic pretense, for he must obscure the actual scientific work done on empathy (and there is quite a lot of research spanning many years) to advance his point and then smuggle into his formulation the utilitarian moral maxim, “the greatest good for the greatest number.”  He asserts that empathy is biased, but his own presuppositions bias his assertions.  For example, he is certain of his moral clarity when he cites statistics to decide which issues should receive moral priority (e.g., Holloway vs. the Sudan) but never justifies ethically why anyone should use statistics in this way.  He simply applies the utilitarian assumption as if his readers should see the moral superiority of his methods.  Moreover, he holds certain views that he thinks everyone should share (e.g., global warming should morally concern everyone) without explaining why these issues should cause moral concern.  Since he is an evolutionist, after all, the extinctions expected from the projected warming of the earth might be the best thing ever to happen from the standpoint of the next dominant life form, just as the extinction of the dinosaurs was terrific news for mammals.  So even from within his own model, his moral concerns over the presumed warming of earth may well be “biased, innumerate, concrete, and myopic,” simply obstacles in the way of a brave new world trying to be born—a world that Bloom is too blind to see.

To be fair, Bloom does admit that reason alone will not lead to moral behavior and caring.  That is remarkably honest.  This, however, does not improve his case.  What he suggests must be added to reason as a motivator simply scuttles his argument.  He posits compassion to serve that role, but that merely causes greater confusion. Compassion, like empathy, is emotive, concrete, and sympathetic.  It is unclear how including this characteristic into the moral equation will exclude the bias he desperately wants to avoid.

Why can’t reason do the job alone?  Perhaps without knowing it, Bloom answers that question.  He points to how advocates of opposing views seek to use empathy to sway public opinion.  If one is in favor of abortion rights, one employs reason to motivate empathy for the pregnant mother; if one is pro-life, one employs reason to motivate empathy for the unborn child.  Empathy is of no real help but becomes the mere tool that reasoning seeks to activate in behalf of chosen presuppositions.  But reason offers no help, either.  It, too, is guided by the very same presuppositions.

What causes a person to choose one set of presuppositions over another?  From what Bloom says, the likely source will surely be training and cultural experience, not reason.  Why?  According to Bloom, reason alone cannot resolve the ethical dilemma.  It awaits the adoption of presuppositions.  Something must condition the reason to choose ethical behavior; else, reason will employ its power to achieve immoral ends.  Bloom has dismissed empathy as a candidate to serve this role, so he needs a replacement.  What does he choose?  Perhaps mystically, he comes up with compassion as his substitute, though what he even means by the term is uncertain.   So empathy is out, replaced by a very fuzzy notion of compassion.  Why that’s important will become clear in a moment.

It’s worth repeating at this juncture that Bloom begins by crediting reason as humankind’s moral guide.  That is the source from which civilization develops systems that improve the moral state of people.  In what he now claims, however, reason is just as satisfied achieving “immoral” aims.”  (So much for reason as the chief instrument of moral improvement)  Consequently, it needs a motivator or governor to keep it from embracing the “dark side.”  Bloom then takes us back to sentiment, which is what he desperately attempted to escape at the beginning.  The longer he argues his case against empathy, the more incoherent his reasoning becomes.  He uses abstractions without doing his readers the courtesy of defining them.  That throws everything into a murky swamp of rhetoric.  Paradoxically, to serve as reason’s motivator, he now relies on another abstraction, “compassion,” a term that many often use as a synonym for “empathy.”  We desperately need good definitions here, but Bloom won’t come up with any.

Playing Games with Definitions

The problem with Bloom’s thinking is simply this:  Empathy is an abstract term.  Unless that term receives an operational definition, we can’t even discuss it, let alone explore it. scientifically.  We can’t know what the term means with any precision.  Bloom throws names around, such as David Hume, Adam Smith, and Peter Singer, but he never gives a satisfactory operational definition to empathy.  No, not even when he briefly mentions neuroscience or refers to some of the research literature!  Instead, he keeps going back to philosophy and philosophers.  He seems satisfied to leave the reader with literary impressions rather than scientific definitions.

He does admit that part of the problem is the term itself.  Some people, he says, use empathy to mean “everything good.”  If people mean that, he says, he’s “all for it.”   That’s incredible!  I can’t imagine a physicist so imprecise as to say, “If what you mean by gravity is that things fall down, I’m all for it.”  Imprecision is the enemy of science.  The only way I can explain how Bloom could accept the imprecise “everything good” as acceptable would be to postulate that his own definition of empathy is equally imprecise.  Or, perhaps, he just doesn’t care.

Fortunately, other researchers (and there is a wealth of literature on this topic) clearly address the operational definition of empathy before they report and interpret their experimental results.  That is good research technique, and their bibliographies are readily available.  I would presume that Bloom would meet the standard of due diligence before making global statements.  Unfortunately, he doesn’t.

Why is this important?  It’s a matter of definition.  As I have said, unless we provide operational definitions for abstract terms, we can’t understand what we are talking about.  Scientific investigation becomes impossible.  For example, do you believe in a democratic system of selecting political leaders?  Suppose you say, “Yes, I believe in a democratic process.”  “Good,” I reply.  “What I mean by democracy is doing what I tell you to do.  That’s real democracy.  Here’s my list of things that I want you to get done.  Come back when you are finished.  I’ll have another list.”

You might reply that this is not what you had in mind by democracy.  Frankly, I wouldn’t blame you, but unless we make our definitions of democracy clear at the start, we won’t know immediately that we are referring to two entirely different things. That will emerge as the surprise when I hand you your “to do” list.  This is not a silly example, by the way.  Rousseau saw man in chains, and he wanted man to be free.  He recognized, however, that many might object to the freedom he offered.    No problem.  Rousseau postulated that freedom is what society as a whole longed for.  That longing became, for Rousseau, the General Will.  So, if a person resisted being free, the General Will would force the person to be free.  Now that’s a tidy bit of reasoning that Bloom could warm up to.

Avoiding dialectical games like that in the pursuit of scientific understanding makes good sense, but making good sense is something Bloom manages to avoid.  That brings us back to Bloom’s use of compassion to induce moral and caring behavior.  Without empathy, Bloom lacks a motivator of the behavior he wants to see.  He needs something, he says, that “will fill the gap.”  For Bloom, compassion is the candidate, but just how that might work to “fill the gap” is more than puzzling.

Vague Abstractions and Concrete Arrogance

Empathy is an abstract term, but so is compassion.  Now we are juggling at least two undefined abstract terms.  Replacing empathy with compassion merely puts the conversation deeper into the swamp.  First, we need an operational definition to understand the term we want to dismiss (empathy); second, we need another to understand the term we want to substitute (compassion).   Morality is also an abstract term, and Bloom hasn’t’ really given a clear definition to that, either.  As Bloom plunges deeper into the dark, he apparently thinks that he is making sense, but adding additional, undefined layers to his model merely makes things darker.  It doesn’t help.

Ultimately, Bloom wants people to do what he wants them to do.  They are not listening, and that annoys him.  His annoyance, however, is the real focus.  He’s not talking science.  He’s simply frustrated socially and politically.  If people do what he wants, that’s moral.  If they don’t, he finds that troubling and even immoral.  Apparently, he is so sure about that he’s published a book on the topic and gives lectures.  He expects people to read his book and to listen to his lectures.  He also expects them to pay attention.  What does he want?  Some might say that he’s demanding empathy.  He wants his readers to stop caring about what they care about; instead, they should start caring about what Bloom cares about.  Incidentally, this serves as a reasonable summary of Professor Bloom’s ideas on empathy.  Why a reader should comply, however, is a question that he cannot answer.  In fact, he does not even try.  He simply assumes that others should care about what he thinks and do what he says.

Why would he make such an assumption?  I can think of two reasons.  First, he’s arrogant enough to confuse his biases for compassion; second, he is confused enough to mistake his arrogance for reason.  He has tricked himself into believing that his views are somehow scientific; consequently, he cannot see the biases he smuggles into his own arguments.  But moral judgments without rationalized foundations but possessing political preferences derived from an undisclosed political philosophy can provide neither tools of scientific analysis nor insight for philosophical discussion.  What we have instead is a lengthy opinion piece.

Conclusion

If Bloom is right about empathy, he has not proved his case—far from it.  His arguments lack the rigor of scientific investigation but make pretense to scientific authority.  That’s a pity.  I would expect better from a secular scholar teaching at Yale than carefully selected, unrepresentative references from existing literature, refusal to clarify terms operationally, the admixture of political opinion, and the subtle assumption of utilitarian ethics.  What he offers up is an uninspiring hodge-podge of materialistic reductionism accented, ironically enough, with mysticism and speculation.  He provides no insights on humankind’s actual moral improvement.

For the moment, therefore, empathy’s positive reputation remains unscathed.  Men and women of goodwill may use it to persuade their communities to respond to issues in the public’s best interests.  And Christians may confidently use their empathy to follow Christ’s command, “Love your neighbor as yourself.”  We may not be perfect in our efforts.  That is something utilitarian moral theory’s “consequentialism” seems to demand. But imperfection does not make our empathy subject to Professor Bloom’s criticisms.  A world governed by his principles would prove that.  It would not be attractive.  Should he give it an experimental try somewhere, certainly others would be willing to join him.  With optimistic enthusiasm, they will formally ban empathy and build their culture.  Then we could see if “rational compassion” could ignite an ethical renaissance on earth and recreate Eden.  If it does, the rest of us will admit error, dispose of our empathy, and seek entrance into paradise.   Somehow, however, I think Bloom would fall short of the ideal objective.  A society in which people think and act the way that Professor Bloom would like—political opinions, news coverage, and all–may prove less frustrating to him, but it really doesn’t sound like a moral paradise.  It doesn’t even sound that interesting.

In conclusion, I offer the good professor some advice.

A Personal Word to Professor Bloom

I am sorry, Dr. Bloom, that people don’t behave the way you would like them to.  I feel your pain.  But please empathize with my position.  Your frustrations provide no justification for shoddy science or amateur philosophy pretending to be science.  I would very much like to see you give this presentation before the American Philosophical Association.  Moreover, the analysis you extend to empathy I would like to see extended to beauty, reason, truth, logic, morality, or any other academically or culturally important abstract term of which we might think.  It would be great fun to see what damage we could do.  We could argue that the very notion of logic gives birth to invalid reasoning or that truth is actually the source of all lies.  Then again, that would take time and effort.  Most of us have actual work to do. 

SOURCES

Bloom, Paul. Against empathy: the case for rational compassion. London: The Bodley Head, 2017. Web.

https://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2014/03/the-war-on-reason/357561/

http://www.vhemt.org/

 

Resources on Empathy

http://psycnet.apa.org/journals/cou/43/3/261/

http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/1520-6696(198401)20:1%3C38::AID-JHBS2300200106%3E3.0.CO;2-1/full

http://cultureofempathy.com/References/NewsPaper/

http://www.goodtherapy.org/blog/psychpedia/empathy

http://www.emotionalcompetency.com/empathy.htm


FOUR IRRITATING FALLACIES—MONTY PYTHON STYLE

March 1, 2017

witch-trialAs Demonstrated in a Witch Trial

Mistakes in reasoning are common in everyday life. From politics to commercials to serious business discussions, logical fallacies arise to derail our thinking and smash our arguments. But we often jump willingly to our conclusions. We don’t recognize our reasoning mistakes, and that’s a pity. So here is something that you can use, while Monty Python entertains.

To help you keep your own reasoning on track, here is a wonderful video clip from Monty Python and the Holy Grail that illustrates at least four rather nasty but common logical fallacies: name-calling, undistributed middle term, false cause, and false authority. My explanations below will elaborate on the video’s fallacies so that you may follow the action and understand why others jump to conclusions. Your mission? That’s simple. Don’t follow the video’s example in your own life—where it really matters!

Here is the video clip link: Monty Python Witch Trial: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=X2xlQaimsGg

Fallacy 1: Name Calling (the Personal Attack)

Villagers bring to the Lord of the Manor (the knight who owns the land) a woman they believe to be a witch. To make her appear guilty, they dress her as a witch, even adding to her face a crooked carrot to simulate a deformed nose. The Lord of the Manor asks the villagers how they know that she is a witch. They point to her appearance, but they are forced to admit that they dressed her to look that way. To recover from this failed attempt, one villager claims that she turned him into a newt. Since he obviously isn’t a lizard now, the villager claims, with some embarrassment, that he simply got better.

These all qualify under the heading of the Fallacy of Name Calling (ad Hominem: to the man), a fallacy that attempts to undermine what another claims or argues by discrediting that person’s character or motives, typically by attributing charges of wrongdoing, immoral behavior, or untrustworthiness. This is a fallacy because a person’s character or motives are irrelevant to the truth of his or her statements. Even if a person has a reason to lie, the truth of what he or she says depends upon whether or not the statements accurately describe the real world, not the person’s virtue or lack of it. Even the most virtuous can have lousy observation skills or misinterpret what’s before them. The truth of a statement, what logicians call soundness, depends upon accuracy, not morality.

Fallacy 2: Undistributed Middle Term (Cf., Equivocation and False Analogy)

As the villagers push the accused before the Lord of the Manor, we get a lesson in faulty class inclusion. Proper class inclusion assumes that if one group is included in another, then the members of both will necessarily share common characteristics. We expect that because the included group is simply a subdivision within the same class. The shared characteristics are “universally distributed” within the class, so all members of any included class must also have them. That’s what logicians mean by a “distributed middle term.” For example, look at this logically valid argument:

“Reptiles are cold-blooded animals. This snake is a reptile. Consequently, it is a cold-blooded animal.” (Reptiles constitute a class characterized by being cold-blooded. The snake is included as a subclass of this larger class. Consequently, we logically conclude that it has the same characteristic)

The Fallacy of an Undistributed Middle Term occurs when the items we compare are not members of the same class but merely seem to share an incidental characteristic. The logical mistake occurs when the two classes are equated on the basis of the incidental, common characteristic. This is equivocal. For example, both rams and bulls have horns, but these animals belong to different classes. The horns are only an incidental similarity. Equating the two classes of animals would be a mistake. Though they both have horns, this fact does not put them in the same class, any more than a car and a horse sharing the same color could be classified as the same things. In fact, the horns of these two animals are not really the same, just similar. The Fallacy of the Undistributed Middle Term makes a shared, similar feature the illicit basis for equating two different classes of things. Like this:

“Rams have horns. Bulls have horns. Consequently, Rams are Bulls.”

Watch what happens as the Lord of the Manor tells the villagers that there are ways to determine if the accused is a witch. He explains that witches burn (a characteristic). Why do they burn? Well, wood also burns (the same characteristic), so witches are made of wood (that equates two classes of different items on the basis of an incidental but shared characteristic). This is the Fallacy of the Undistributed Middle Term. Following this form of reasoning would allow us to easily lose our way logically. (For example, Mr. Smith has two feet; Mrs. Smith has two feet. Consequently, Mr. Smith is Mrs. Smith).

Now what the duck’s weight has to do with it is anyone’s guess. Of course, this is an example of the same fallacy. Two different things may have the same weight, but that shared quality does not make them the same. Take a survey. What would people prefer: a pound of duck feathers or a pound of gold? If someone tells you that the two are the same, don’t go into business with that person. You’ll be sorry.

The Undistributed Middle Term can deflect any reasoning into pure silliness.

Fallacy 3: False Cause

In fact, this is what happens in the video. Wood floats, the Lord of the Manor says. He then asks what else floats? King Arthur, who has been observing in the background, confidently answers that it is a duck. The Lord of the Manor affirms that answer as the correct one. What does this mean? Drawing out answers from the villagers, the Lord of the Manor establishes that if the accused equates to a duck, then that equates to being wood, which equates to being a witch. This reasoning, however, is an example of the False Cause fallacy (Post Hoc, Ergo Proctor Hoc: after this, therefore because of this).

Why? Even if we take the humorous argument seriously, not all wooden items are witches. In fact, the Lord of the Manor says this explicitly, “And what do you burn other than witches.” The answer? “Wood,” says one of the villagers, to the Lord of the Manor’s approval. The video also admits that some bridges are made of wood, without directing the villagers to burn all wooden bridges on the charge of witchcraft. Clearly, the Lord of the Manor and the villagers know that not all wood comes from witches. Consequently, what the Lord of the Manor must be claiming is that when one becomes a witch, that “witchy” quality turns the person into wood.

But even taking this silly argument seriously, proving that the accused is wood does NOT demonstrate logically that she is a witch. This is a False Cause, for being wood is not necessarily the result of being a witch; otherwise, wooden bridges and all wooden things would be constructed of witches. In other words, a witch may be wood, but not all wood comes from witches. So even if the accused turns out to be wood, that might be the result of a cause quite different from what the villagers allege. In other words, demonstrating that something is wood does not prove a “witchy” origin. It simply suggests a woody one.

Fallacy 4: False Authority

The Lord of the Manor proposes a simple diagnostic test for the accused. If the accused weighs the same as a duck, that proves she is a witch. Why? Sharing the duck’s weight makes her equivalent to wood, for a duck is equivalent to wood. If she is wood, then she is a witch. So he proposes to use his weighing scales to test her. With a duck on one side and the accused on the other, the scales measure both to be identical. This proves, according to the Lord of the Manor, that the accused is a witch.

But accepting this conclusion requires one to assume that the Lord of the Manor knows what he is talking about. Nothing in evidence confirms such expertise. In fact, quite the opposite. His logic has already proven quite faulty. Moreover, his rank in society and personal land holdings don’t offer him insight into the paranormal. He is, consequently, a False Authority (the fallacy Ad Verecundiam: to authority). Moreover, using the results of the measurement as evidence assumes the authority of the scales. Even if one accepts the silly premise of the test, this will not permit assuming that the scales are accurate. Consequently, what the measurement means is uncertain. Relying upon the unchecked scales, therefore, is also an example of False Authority.

So there you have some fallacies committed on purpose–for your viewing pleasure–by Monty Python. To follow up on other logical fallacies that can get you into trouble, you might find the link below useful.

Logical Fallacies Handlist: https://web.cn.edu/kwheeler/fallacies_list.html


Neither Victims nor Executioners—A Christian Meditation on Albert Camus

February 24, 2017

camus“In such a world of conflict, a world of victims and executioners, it is the job of thinking people, not to be on the side of the executioners.”

Several collections of quotations on the web attribute the words cited above to the French writer and existentialist, Albert Camus.  It’s a powerful quote that arrests the imagination of the perceptive reader; a reader who has followed with shock and revulsion the chronicles of mindless assassins who have roamed the earth these past forty years to harvest the fruit of massacre.  Though the quote is striking, Camus did not write it.  It comes from A People’s History of the United States, written by the historian and playwright, Howard Zinn.

Doubtless, this was Zinn’s summary of Camus’ concluding words from an article entitled, “Toward Dialogue: Neither Victims nor Executioners.”  It appeared as the last of eight chapters in a collection of his essays, published as Camus at Combat: Articles and Editorials (1944-1947).  These essays conveyed his experiences and reflections as a partisan in the French Underground resisting Nazi occupation.

Though Zinn’s summary is eloquently concise, the words Camus actually wrote also make the point powerfully, but they are far more uncomfortable, as we will see a little later.  Camus had seen the carnage of combat, political betrayal, the murder of innocents, and the near triumph of a brutal and irrational ideology.  He had seen France trampled by German jackboots, the French army nearly destroyed, and the nation’s legitimate government replaced by the Nazi Vichy regime.  With tears, he had witnessed the resultant brutality and injustice inflicted upon the people of France by collaborating countrymen, who offered themselves as tightly fitting gloves to embrace Hitler’s iron fist.  Before Camus’ eyes, centuries of civilization had easily crumbled before an irrational barbarism, giving the young writer a brutal intellectual shock—one that forged his notion of existential absurdity.

I do not hold to Camus’ existentialist philosophy, though I respect the man and appreciate the experiences that forged his thinking.  Some of his moral views, I believe, made even Camus uncomfortable.  In 1942, he wrote The Stranger, a story of death, revenge, and murder, told blandly by one who awaited a prison execution.  Critics note the moral and emotional indifference in that story, a coldness that seems to conflict with Camus’ 1947 novel, The Plague. That tale depicts how different inhabitants of a city manage the realities of a deadly pestilence, as each personally experiences the very real threat of death.  Are the two stories in conflict?  Camus would reject the claim, saying that both novels are simply case studies in the absurd.  Moreover, if the critic found this answer unacceptable, he might then add that the absurdity of life makes even that OK.

Of the two, The Plague is a much more satisfying story to me, because it is more human, more real, and more poignant.  The account of a city’s battle with plague captures that sense of helplessness to which catastrophic events often reduce our minds and emotions.  Camus brutally describes how such events force us to choose and to act even when we are powerless.  The possibility of such overpowering events ever lurks just below our consciousness, but society and technology successfully conspire to conceal the possibility from our awareness, and so it is repressed.  But such events do occur, and the survivor of a crushing, overpowering catastrophe will remain forever changed, never again feeling perfectly secure or in control.

Therefore, though pushed socially from our awareness, we still know how weakly we grasp onto what is dearest to us and how easily some force might forever rip from our presence the ones we love, valued possessions, and even our dreams.  We don’t like to think about this, but we still know it.  Consequently, a reader will quickly identify with the vulnerabilities of Camus’ characters, as well as their losses as the The Plague’s story unfolds.  The very act of living–no matter the station in life, abilities, or weaknesses–necessarily implies both loss and its threat.  We mourn when the former occurs, but some may live in constant fear of the latter.  So what we love is always at risk, and there is no escape.

With a remorseless hand, Camus shows us in The Plague the human condition that we each share.  With a gentler stroke, however, he delivers this human message for those who will understand.  Let me do my best to summarize it.  Life is uncertain and overwhelming, and there are no “happy endings.”  But the choices we make, even when we feel helpless, are the very things that make us what we are, that define us as human beings.  So events are not so important; neither are outcomes of ultimate consequence.  Our power to choose makes us intrinsically valuable, not the events or outcomes of our lives.  Of such intrinsic value, the things we measure by the ticks of a clock can know nothing.  Our choices, consequently, are far too valuable to sacrifice upon the altar of what happens to us.  That would be like sacrificing ourselves to rough-hewn idols of stone.  For our choices transform us in the face of life’s events and outcomes.  That transformation makes us human, and that is our ultimate value.

I do not share Camus’ philosophy.  I am a Christian, and Camus considered religious faith intellectual suicide.  Nonetheless, I feel a sense of kinship with the author of The Plague, and I resonate to its message.  But unlike Camus, I believe that God has made each of us the bearer of his image and invites us by his grace to touch the lives of others with justice, love, and truth.  That we do in this world through our choices, following Christ’s example.  That is what gives meaning and purpose to our lives.  It is our ultimate source of value, not the events and outcomes of life itself.

As Christians, however, we often focus on what happens to us, rather than on the choices we make in response to life’s challenges and uncertainties.  These choices, however, either give our faith its substance or betray it.  Nonetheless, we find our focus attracted to events and outcomes, not the authentic choices that build our faith.  We want charitable programs to work as planned, church attendance to grow, faith events to run smoothly, illness to end in health, and life crises to resolve in satisfactory ways.   We also count ourselves successful when we achieve our educational, career, and personal goals.  We measure our lives by the tick-tock of events and outcomes and judge our personal value by how impressively we adorn the face of the clock.

God does not measure in this way; consequently, Camus’ message from The Plague speaks to us with the authority of an apostle’s letter.  He admonishes us to examine how our choices define us in the midst of life’s pressures.  He also cautions that life’s challenges often defy our ability to overcome them.  Even the most fortunate and sheltered among us will face that unpleasant truth at least one time in life.  Consequently, when we face the loss of all that seems valuable to us, the choices we then make will disclose who we truly are.  Camus ends his sermon with a question, “Will we face that storm as human beings, or will we sacrifice ourselves to pointless idols?”

Though Camus rejected religious faith, this sermon message surpasses most homilies that I have heard from pulpits.  The Plague offers Christians of all stripes serious food for moral reflection.  Moreover, I would venture that Camus, himself, found the human face he portrays in that novel more encouraging and more consistent with his own character.  The Stranger, on the other hand, was more like his nightmare, a fear of what humankind might become should the race sacrifice itself to idols.

How can I be sure?  Camus’ last paragraph in “Toward Dialogue: Neither Victims nor Executioners” provides the proof—the words that Howard Zinn summarized.  (Remember?  I told you we would get to Camus actual quote.)  In many ways, Camus’ words are more powerful than Zinn’s clever summary.  For he speaks as a prophet who warns of a judgment to come that will require each of us to choose a side.

Camus challenges us in an uncomfortable way to elect a future—a future that will divide the world into two warring groups, each with a different method of warfare.  One might be termed a “culture of death,” which revels in the humiliation and blood of the vulnerable and celebrates their death.  The other is a “culture of life,” which refuses to stand on the necks of the weak and preaches a message of peace throughout the earth.  The former culture arms itself with formidable weapons; the latter, with words.  Who will win the struggle?  Again, it’s not the outcome that is important.  It is the choice.  There is only one honorable one, Camus says, and he has no question which one it is.

“Now I can end.  What I think needs to be done at the present time is simply this:  in the midst of a murderous world, we must decide to reflect on murder and choose.  If we can do this, then we will divide ourselves into two groups: those who, if need be, would be willing to commit murder or become accomplices to murder, and those who would refuse to do so with every fiber of their being.  Since this awful division exists, we would be making some progress, at least, if we were clear about it.  Across five continents, an endless struggle between violence and preaching will rage in the years to come.  And it is true that the former is a thousand times more likely to succeed than the latter.  But I have always believed that if people who placed their hope in the human condition were mad, those who despaired of events were cowards.  Henceforth there will be only one honorable choice: to wager everything on the belief that in the end words will prove stronger than bullets.”

 –Albert Camus, “Toward Dialogue:  Neither Victims Nor Executioners” (Arthur Goldhammer’s Translation)

That quote, I think, identifies where Camus personally stands between The Stranger and The Plague.  He is by no means cold and morally indifferent.  He is passionate about redeeming the future.  He would fight plagues.

Moreover, the prophecy he fervently offers in these words has proved remarkably accurate.  The violence he predicted then today defiles the world, its marching jackboots spilling blood across five continents.  Soldiers of clashing armies kill one another with ever more powerful weapons and make victims of mothers and children, of the old and the sick.  They poison new generations with a legacy of hatred and hold the future hostage.

As Christians, we can join with Camus to preach a message of peace against the violence, against the guns and bullets.  But in Christ, we have a promise, an unfailing hope.  Thus we enjoy a confidence that Camus did not possess.  For our Lord teaches us that his Word created the heavens and the earth.  It is that very Word that he has instructed us to take to the nations, the Gospel of peace.  He also has promised that the gates of hell will not prevail against his Church, the bearers of his Word.  The violent, therefore, may fill their armories to the brim with bullets.  No matter.  Even should they take our lives, their weaponry doesn’t stand a chance.  Christ’s Word will prevail, and earth will one day be at peace.  That is the promise, and all of Christ’s people will share in that victory.

In Christ, therefore, we confidently choose to side with the victims, encouraging them with our faith.  Their cause will be heard, and God’s justice will be done.  We may then freely turn with hope to face the executioner’s bullets, a hymn of praise and a prayer of forgiveness on our lips.  Though the events and outcomes of life may come to an end, we will yet see victory.  For our choices have kept the faith.  We know who we are and in whom we have believed.  We have nothing to fear.

 

 


Ten Top Challenges for Re-Entry

February 22, 2017

At Corrections Corporation of America, Michelle Ryder, director of Treatment and Behavioral Programs, and Jill Gillian, manager of Reentry Services, have identified 10 of the most common challenges for individuals reentering society:  They recommend that an inmate begin addressing these issues prior to release.  They provide a foundation of support that makes re-entry more achievable.

  1. I.D. and Official Papers (Social Security Card, Birth Certificate, Driver’s License)

Without having their official papers in order, an ex-offender will not be able to find housing or employment, operate vehicles, qualify for credit, get insurance, or do a number of other things they will have to do in order to make their re-entry successful.

  1. Finding Benefits that Offenders May Receive

A felony conviction may interfere with an ex-offender’s ability to qualify for public assistance.  Disability, food stamps, and housing assistance may be affected.  Ex-offenders need knowledgeable guidance to identify public assistance and resources for which they qualify.

  1. Finding Reliable Transportation for Work and Daily Living

Ex-offenders will probably not have access to a car.  They will need to know their city’s bus system and learn how to get around using the bus to get to work, to do shopping, and to go to medical appointments.  This challenge can throw barriers in the way of employment, proper childcare, and getting to required appointments set up by parole officers.  In addition to knowing bus routes and schedules, ex-offenders will need to learn resources for bus passes.

  1. Affordable and Adequate Housing

Those without a safe place to live are more likely to recidivate, especially at-risk females.  Helping offenders assess their eligibility for safe public housing or identifying relatives who might be willing to provide shelter, even temporarily, will improve the ex-offender’s chances for success.

  1. Health Care and Health Insurance

For personal and public health reasons, it’s important for recently-released individuals to attend to their health care needs after release. This means finding medical providers and perhaps insurance programs that can meet their medical needs on a sliding scale basis.

  1. Support for Sobriety

Ex-offenders with substance abuse histories will need sobriety support.  Without, the statistics say that they will re-offend  and return to jail.  Self-help groups and counselors must be part of pre-release planning.  Follow through is essential.

  1. Reconnecting to Family

Many ex-offenders have families, but incarceration makes reconnecting difficult.  Spouses may be estranged, but the children need both parents.  Ex-offenders need counseling to navigate these difficult waters.  Even reconnecting to parents and siblings can prove difficult and stressful.  .

  1. Reading, Writing, and Re-Entry

An education not only improves an offender’s quality of life, but it also helps them qualify for work once they reenter society.  Upgrading work and literacy skills is a major tool to help ex-offenders avoid re-offending.

  1. Finding and Keeping a Decent Job

Getting a job is critical to an ex-offender’s success, and once they find employment, it can be challenging to maintain that job. Teaching job readiness skills, such as resume building and interviewing skills, as well as handling potential issues such as peer relationships and job stress, will help the ex-offender achieve healthy goals.

  1. Money Management (bank accounts, bills, child support, etc.)

Upon release and finding employment, ex-offenders soon encounter the responsibility that comes with paying for housing and utility bills, as well as fulfilling other financial obligations, such as victim restitution or child support. Helping ex-offenders prepare for these situations by teaching practical life skills, such as how to create a budget, open and maintain a bank account and apply for credit, will reduce the money management stresses of re-entry.

By David Richardson

SOURCE: 

http://www.cca.com/insidecca/addressing-the-top-10-inmate-reentry-challenges


ANNUAL DAMAGE TO KIDS? TWENTY CITIES AND COUNTING

February 16, 2017
fort-wayne

Fort Wayne–Pop: 250,000

According to a 2015 Child Trends report (“Parents Behind Bars: What Happens to Their Children”), 1 in 14 American children (about 7%) has experienced the absence of at least one parent because of a prison sentence. That’s up from the last estimate in 2007, which put the percentage at 2%. The 2007 percentage comes to about 1.7 million children. According to Child Trends, that percentage might now approach 5 million. That’s nearly three times larger than what experts recorded just eight years ago.

To help get a practical of idea of what this figure means, take a mid-sized Indiana city, such as Fort Wayne. Currently, that city has a population of about a quarter million people. Now do some math. The 5 million children who currently have lost a parent to prison would fill 20 cities the size of Fort Wayne. No adults, mind you, just children. To peg the rate of growth from just eight years ago, the 2007 estimate would fill between six to seven cities. By the end of 2015, the number of children who had seen a parent behind prison bars added the equivalent of thirteen more mid-sized cities—an annual total of twenty municipalities.

As things stand, that number will continue to grow. That’s twenty cities and counting. No one can favor that kind of “urban growth” or call it healthy for families. Research has already documented the lasting damage to children caused by the loss of a parent to prison.  In an article published by Education Week (“Children of Inmates Seen at Risk”: 2/25/15), reporter Sarah Sparks summarizes the research findings on the negative effects.  These include:

·      Behavioral problems,

·      Language and speech delays,

·      Physical and psychological illness,

·      Lower academic achievement,

·      Lower high school graduation rates,

·     Lower college entrance and graduation rates, and

·      Greater likelihood of incarceration in later life.

Damaging American children in this way is both unacceptable and unsustainable.  It might even be called child abuse.  Justifiably, the courts often send adults guilty of that crime to prison.  What happens to a society that treats children as collateral damage in its efforts to control of crime?  Ironically, that remains uncertain.  But without a solution, America will eventually find out–as the collateral damage matures to adulthood.

SOURCES:

http://www.childtrends.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/10/2015-42ParentsBehindBars.pdf

http://www.edweek.org/ew/articles/2015/02/25/parents-incarceration-takes-toll-on-children-studies.html


Are “Vouchers” and “Parental Choice” the Real Issues in Education?

February 14, 2017

warrenSenator Elizabeth Warren has apparently changed her mind on vouchers. In a book she co-authored in 2003, The Two-Income Trap: Why Middle-Class Parents Are (Still) Going Broke, she supported them. In her challenge to Betsy DeVoss’ nomination as Secretary of the Department of Education, she has changed her mind.

Her views on Trump’s nominees don’t concern me. I would expect her to be critical. She is, after all, a Democratic senator. That’s her job, so to speak. Moreover, I don’t mind a politician, or any thinking person, changing a position on an important issue. That should be the result, however, of a logical process that says, “I was mistaken in my assessment, and here are the reasons that have forced me to change my mind.” But we don’t see anything approaching an explanation here. Instead, we see pure partisan outrage. It’s comic and irrelevant.

Switching views for partisan reasons or to gain a supposed political advantage suggests a thought process motivated by short-term considerations, not long-term solutions. Though a professor who presumably cares about education, Senator Warren insists on missing the point totally. Her shrill irrelevancy should entertain her detractors and disappoint her constituency. The issue of education deserves better, for it affects the future workforce, crime statistics, the census in state and federal prison systems, international business competitiveness, and a host of other topics. Senator Warren may not like DeVoss, but I have another question for her–and for other senators on either side of the aisle.

The real issue with school vouchers is not public versus private education. Even parental choice doesn’t quite capture the problem. The real issue is education that prepares students for their futures or education that condemns young people to restricted opportunities in a world economy where they will be unable to compete with better educated young people–nationally or globally. Those on the Left and the Right had better decide where the future is going to take place–with their political base or with young people now entering school.

America’s educational system is not working–especially for minorities and the poor. That is not a matter for debate. It is the truth and constitutes a real and present danger to the republic. We entrust elected officials to address threats such as this. When they fail to do so, whether they come from the Left or the Right, they betray the nation’s trust. Citizens should not reward that betrayal in future elections with their votes.

Despite emergency legislation (e.g., “No Child Left Behind), America’s educational decline has been going on for decades. U.S. business now spends billions of dollars annually on the remedial training of its workers. As foreign nations make impressive gains, American children fall behind in both literacy and math. America is now failing to prepare a new generation of young Americans. Many of the unprepared from the last generation we now house in the nation’s prisons. Mass incarceration is a scandal. Now experts tell us that this next generation will be less educated and less skilled than their parents. That’s also a scandal–and a tragedy. Is the solution building more prisons? That’s no way to maintain a world-class economy.

So here is my question, Senator Warren. Please share it with other senators–Republicans and Democrats. Compared to the rest of the world, U.S. education is expensive and mediocre. What are you and your colleagues going to do about it?

SOURCES:

https://www.theatlantic.com/education/archive/2013/12/american-schools-vs-the-world-expensive-unequal-bad-at-math/281983/#main-content

https://rankingamerica.wordpress.com/category/education/

The U.S. ranks 1st in prisoners

http://whotv.com/2013/12/03/lagging-behind-us-education-ranks-36th-worldwide/

http://www.huffingtonpost.com/2013/09/06/illiteracy-rate_n_3880355.html

http://www.statisticbrain.com/number-of-american-adults-who-cant-read/

http://www.greatschools.org/gk/articles/u-s-students-compare/

https://nces.ed.gov/fastfacts/display.asp?id=1

http://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2015/02/02/u-s-students-improving-slowly-in-math-and-science-but-still-lagging-internationally/


A Logical Fallacy Explains Why Change Is Not always Good

February 14, 2017

deterioration

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 


THE GREAT WHITE WHALE OFFERS A FEW WORDS TO 21ST CENTURY AMERICA

February 12, 2017

moby-dickFor those who have prophetic souls, the study of literature can be quite satisfying, especially if it is done outside the Academy. For inside the lecture hall, post-modern vampires will drain all life from a great novel, poem, or play, and leave it in your hands crumbling to dust. But let great authors on their own terms speak to you, and their words will elucidate the past and even show you the future.  One such novelist is Herman Melville, author of Moby-Dick. His voice has something to teach about America’s possible future, and the angry voices we hear around us today would do well to listen. Through his great white whale, Melville offers a prophetic warning.

MOBY-DICK: AN ANALOGICAL TALE

Though several movies now tell its story, Moby-Dick (first published in 1851) offers a challenge to moviemakers. Melville’s masterpiece, which 19th-century critics and the reading public failed to recognize, is a daunting and complicated book. The plot is hard to condense suitably in a few lines. I would not even try it. But as a child some years ago, I remember reading a TV Guide listing that provided a summary in just a brief phrase, “Madman chases whale.” Of course, that completely misses the author’s point. It is understandable, however, that moviemakers and listing writers might have difficulty with this novel. The problem for them is that Melville’s story is analogical, not literal. Like a parable, its images provide a vehicle for meaning that lies far beyond them—meaning that many may find uncomfortable.

Commentators note that the story of the Essex, a whaling ship rammed and sunk by a large whale in 1820, inspired Melville’s tale. The real story of the Essex, however, comes from the three-month nightmare at sea endured by those who escaped the sinking ship–the captain and 20 crew members. Of these, only eight survived, included the captain, George Pollard, Jr. That survival ordeal devolved ultimately into cannibalism, but none of that really appears in Melville’s book, so the story of Ahab and the Pequod is not a fictionalized account of Pollard and the Essex.

Instead, it is a prophecy that is even more terrible—one that speaks like an Amos or Joel to America’s soul.

THE STORY’S MEANING

So what does the story mean? It is social criticism, intensely symbolic and razor sharp. It has no more to do with whaling than Jesus’ “Parable of the Sower” has to do with scientific agriculture. Melville simply used whaling and the fate of the Essex as a vehicle to offer America a cautionary tale. During the author’s life, America could not hear his warning; both he and Moby-Dick fell into obscurity. But Melville was a prophet. The tragic outbreak of the Civil War, less than a decade after the novel’s publication, certainly establishes his reputation as a seer, though few at the time noticed. Tragically, he and most of his work remained virtually unknown. Only in the 20th century have critics recognized Moby-Dick as a literary classic and Melville as one of America’s most important authors. Nonetheless, in the 21st century, his prophetic warning remains unheeded, even by the majority of those who have read the adventure. Parables are like that.

What Melville fears in the American character is a perverse, Puritan-like turn of mind that must see all experience in terms of good and evil, pressing everything into that mold—whether or not it fits. Ahab symbolizes how that character responds to deep and personal wounds. He has lost his leg to the great whale. That is the wound. He now seeks a righteous retribution, extending his holy passion through his ship and its crew. Blood for blood, Moby-Dick will pay with its life to satisfy Ahab’s vengeance. But the creature he crusades to destroy is neither good nor evil; it is simply a force of nature and cares nothing for Ahab’s categories. When Ahab crushes all experience into his press of moral vengeance, he pits himself and all who are with him against the forces of reality itself. That challenge brings them all to destruction—save one, Ishmael, the witness. Had the North and the South heeded Melville’s warning, perhaps both sides could have worked to trade pride and righteous indignation to win justice, human dignity, and unity, rather than to beckon so many young men to their deaths, leaving so many widows and orphans and such deep and open racial wounds.

The Pequod symbolizes America; Ahab is a twisted covenant with death that fills the ship’s sails and arrogantly directs her course.  Ishmael is the one born outside that covenant, the one who survives to tell the tale. The mixed crew, assembled from different geographical locations, races, and classes, represents society and culture. The great white whale is the mystery of reality itself, from which all life emerges but ever extends—in sorrow or in joy–beyond human categories and understanding.

America’s nightmare destiny, in Melville’s view, is to use her power and technology in a moral assault upon reality itself in order to destroy what is evil and to establish what is good. That perverse crusade will seek to chisel from what actually exists an idol crafted in its own image—an idol arrogant and cruel, a pseudo-deity that bewitches the nation’s imagination to worship the very act of fabrication, that blinds it to what is real, and then seduces the culture to its own destruction—just as Ahab’s waving dead arm, his body tied fast to the whale by harpoon line, beckons his crew to their deaths. That is the meaning of Melville’s parable; at least, that is the best that I can do.

MOBY-DICK’S MESSAGE TODAY

What might Moby-Dick’s message be to an all too sophisticated 21st-century America? The great white whale might offer some advice. For example, it would not discount the struggle between good and evil. Anyone with a brain and a bit of history knows that this conflict is real. But the ocean beast would simply remind us that we infuse our own unmistakable stink on most of the evil we see yet choose to remain nose blind. A rational crusade to stamp out evil, consequently, would have to begin by stamping out ourselves. That might cause a bit of self-reflection before we elect to raise the banners and to blow the trumpets.

The great whale might also remind us that we keep getting it wrong—on purpose. We like to play games with good and evil. The motive? It is hard to trick people into doing corrupt and brutal things that serve our personal interests. If they think they do it in the name of a noble cause, however, the deceit becomes much easier to pull off. For that transforms “I oppose you” into “You are evil.” Attaching that epithet turns people into worthless things. History teaches that motivated warriors will crush what they perceive as evil far more enthusiastically than they will crush what they see as another human being.

The monster whale would also say that for political, economic, or ideological reasons, we keep twisting what the struggle is. The beast would tell us that we purposely create monsters in order to destroy them, as if it were a particularly satisfying human hobby. It would point out that we do this to avoid basing our moral judgments on any systematic and rational ethical theory, preferring to seek personal affronts and to stir up prejudices to fuel moral outrage. Pretexts are easier. It would also note that we turn opponents into villains with ad hominem attacks, hurling the same assaults against anyone who might venture a defense. Then we elevate those with whom we sympathize to sainthood, overlooking any flaws and imparting to them a purity of motive that we know is most certainly nonsense. This projection, the sea creature would observe, we use to avoid dealing with rational objections and to take the moral offensive against anyone who makes a legitimate criticism.

Finally, Moby-Dick would question why we so eagerly embrace any ideological view—political, religious, social, or economic—when it seduces us to take hysterical fanatical action, even in the face of facts, common sense, and human decency. The creature would wonder, “Why do you risk the lives of others, put our own lives in jeopardy, and destroy what has taken years to build just to stand for dogmatic ideas that cannot tolerate alternative views or negotiate the real world but, instead, demand the mangling and dismemberment of reality to fit imaginary categories and to fuel infantile rage? Even to an uneducated whale, that makes no sense.”

Such advice the great white whale might provide–in simple respect to its creator, Herman Melville. For Moby-Dick’s author warns us not to follow that lifeless, beckoning arm leading to disaster, no matter from what part of our culture it might be waving. So his creature dutifully passes on the counsel but then indifferently swims away and leaves us to our own devices. Forces of nature are like that; they do not care about humankind’s future. But if we learn to listen, with the help of an insightful author, they can help us to face reality with greater wisdom. That is desperately needed during these days in which grim-faced crowds, full of spleen, deliberately step without restraint into the streets and methodically begin knocking peoples’ hats off—or worse.

Sources:

https://archive.org/details/moby_dick_librivox?q=Moby+Dick

http://www.smithsonianmag.com/history/the-true-life-horror-that-inspired-moby-dick-17576/

http://www.massmoments.org/moment.cfm?mid=334